What Use is Philosophy to the Counsellor and Psychotherapist?            Tim LeBon

There is not a close a enough link between the professions of philosophy and counselling. Most counsellors ignore philosophy. For example Egan (1975) recommends a curriculum of ten subjects for trainee counsellors which neglects philosophy altogether. Similarly the insular academic philosophical world does not take much interest in psychotherapy. For example when the current writer had an article published in the magazine Philosophy Now (LeBon, 1994) the editor of the magazine wrote "Tim LeBon .. is training to be an existential psychotherapist, whatever that is" (my italics). This essay will argue that counsellors should be more philosophically aware. I will first argue that those concerned with counselling theory ( i.e. the attempt to explain and justify various counselling approaches ) need to use the philosophy of mind and ethics. I will then go on to examine the more contentious view that philosophy also has a place in the counselling session itself.

 

Philosophy and the theory of counselling

Those who try to appraise counselling theories should undoubtedly be philosophically literate. Every approach to counselling is based on some philosophical assumptions - only more often than not these are left implicit and unexamined. Existentialism depends partly on phenomenology, which is just one answer to the problems of perception and subject-object relationship. Psychoanalysis assumes determinism, which is just one stance in the age-old philosophical problem of free will. Cognitive-behavioural approaches advocate hedonism, the debatable view that pleasure is the only thing of value. Heaton (1990:4) recognises that philosophy has a role to play when he says "Philosophy can be on the sidelines criticising its concepts" but rather throws the point away. I would want to argue that this role is far more important than is usually recognised.

 Two examples, from the philosophy of mind and ethics, will demonstrate how counselling theory can go wrong by being philosophically naive. My first example is how philosophy is used by Sartre to refute the Freudian notion of repression. Repression is supposed to be a useful explanatory concept, especially in connection with self-deception. Initially we are puzzled because when we deceive ourselves we know X but in another sense we believe X to be false. Repression is meant to explain this by positing the existence of a censor which decides that something is too painful for the ego to bear, and so represses it. In Chapter 2 of Being and Nothingness Sartre (1956) points out the infinite regress that is involved in Freud's concept of self-deception. For in repression the censor itself ( rather than the person) must be aware of what is to be repressed and what is conscious. Hence Freud's solution only moves the problem one step further back and in no way is the explanation of self-deception it may appear to be.

 My second example of the need for philosophical awareness in counselling theory comes from ethics. Many humanistic therapists encourage clients to aim for self-actualisation and to avoid "oughts" and "musts". Yet any first-year ethics student will be aware that morality - i.e. that which insists on "oughts" and "musts" - is a necessary check on the individual's selfish urges. Taking the view of an ideal observer of the whole of society, morality ensures that the general welfare is enhanced by the following of rules which may seem to be against individual's short-term interests. This is not to say that all forms of morality are good, nor that any individual will always benefit from being moral - my point is that if people ignore "oughts" and aim only to achieve their own self-fulfilment they will inevitably harm other people, and possibly themselves in the long-run. This is exactly the point van Deurzen-Smith (1988,14-19) makes in criticising such counselling approaches. She cites the case of Frances who, encouraged by a personal-growth group, abandoned her family responsibilities to try to fulfil herself - only to find that the implications of breaking the commitment of marriage were more serious than she realised and "that the ensuing chaos ( when one abandons moral rules) was not attractive at all". A basic awareness of the philosophical relevance of morality would have prevented humanistic theorists taking such a simplistic approach ( though to be fair such an approach is usually coupled with an equally naive faith in human nature which if correct would make morality matter less).

In view of the fact that their client's well-being is of such central importance, it is incredible how little attention is paid to ethics. Counsellors are of course aware that there are ethical implications of their work, but tend to focus on small details (like whether counsellors should keep records of sessions) rather than the more fundamental question of what is happening to the well-being of their client. What is required is more work like that of Holmes and Lindley (1989). They take a broadly utilitarian stance and argue that psychotherapy can be justified in that it increases the autonomy of the client. By turning id into ego and enhancing self-knowledge and self-awareness, therapy enables the client to take control of their life. Increasing public awareness and debate about counselling makes it vital that other theorists enter the public domain to defend the efficacy of their particular approach.

Philosophy and the practice of counselling

The opponents of philosophy have to admit, I think, that philosophy is of use in assessing the theory of counselling, but they may still argue that it is the antithesis of what is required in counselling practice. Surely, they will say, counselling is about being warm and practical - whereas philosophers are notoriously impractical and academic and therefore out of touch with the requirements of a troubled, non-academic client. I will now argue, against this, that in fact there are two distinct ways in which counselling can be a sort of philosophy. These two different ways correspond to the two approaches to philosophy noted by Purton (1993). The first approach to philosophy tries to establish positive conclusions, for example about how to live, whereas the other merely attempts to clarify and question.

 

(i) Philosophy's attempt to provide knowledge used in counselling

The first way that philosophers can contribute is through providing answers to questions relating to the goals of therapy - for example "What is the good life ?" and "How can meaning in life be enhanced ?" Throughout the ages philosophers of various schools have attempted answers to these questions, most notably perhaps the existentialists and utilitarians. Existentialists think that authenticity is important and that people should acknowledge the givens of life - such as the facts that they must create their own meaning, that they are free and that they will die. Hence a certain way of being is advocated - a way of living which is consistent with the values of existentialism. van Deurzen-Smith (1994:20) argues for this sort of use of philosophy in counselling when she says that that counselling is applied philosophy, and counsellors should "investigate and rigorously apply the laws of existence." Conversely utilitarians think that the good life is one that maximises happiness. Hence a utilitarian therapist would encourage clients to examine the consequences of their actions, to look at alternatives, and to be aware of what it is that makes them happy.

Both the existential and utilitarian answers to the "good life" are attractive. However we must be wary as counsellors in using philosophical "knowledge" of this sort too liberally. That I have presented two equally plausible, yet conflicting, accounts of the "good life" should set us on our guard. The problem is that though philosophy may try to establish a body of knowledge, it rarely does so to everyone's satisfaction. Whilst scientists may agree that penicillin cures infections, not all philosophers agree about what is the good life. Nor will they ever, for we are talking about ultimate ends, and because they are ultimate it is impossible to justify them in terms of anything else. So one man may prefer happiness, another authenticity, and nothing anyone can do will prove either wrong. The upshot is that counsellors should not use their philosophical "knowledge" as if it was objective, scientific fact. An alternative is to be very explicit to clients about one's values - so an existential therapist would offer therapy to people and tell them that they offered the client the chance to be more authentic, whereas a cognitive-behaviourist therapist ( perhaps) might tell the client they are there to enhance the client's happiness. As long as this happens then a philosophically-inspired counsellor is in a similar position to a Christian counsellor - values have been agreed between the client and counsellor, and the object is to make the clients life live up to these values. So whilst philosophy of this first sort can be of use, counsellors have to be wary of preaching dogma to the unconverted but easily-influenced client, be it derived from philosophical reflection or religious revelation.

 

(ii) The philosophical approach applied to a client's life

 

There is another, perhaps less controversial way to bring a sort of philosophy into the counselling session. Philosophy is about clarifying, questioning and exploring. Although it has tended to be applied to "big" questions like the meaning of life, there is in fact no limit as to its subject matter. Now suppose we apply philosophy to a client's life. Counsellors can facilitate the clarification of the client's world, the questioning of their assumptions and the exploration of the alternatives they face. This is philosophy in the second of Purton's senses - what Wittgenstein calls "a working on oneself. On one's own interpretations. On one's way of seeing things ... it unties the knots in our thinking" ( 1980:16 ). In this way philosophy can contribute towards the client leading "the examined life".

 

I can give an example from my own therapy about how this sort of counselling can be beneficial. For a long time I was really quite anxious about my future career. I had this definite feeling that I wanted to leave computing, and also that I wanted to get into counselling. Yet I needed to stay in computing to earn money. My counsellor was able to lay before me the assumptions I was making. viz. :-

[1] I want to go into counselling.

[2] I want to leave computing.

[3] I need money.

[4] I cannot go into counselling without leaving computing completely.

 

Step 4 is the unwarranted step that led to my anxiety. My counsellor simply checked whether it was a valid assumption that there had to be such a black and white choice. I immediately realised that there was the option of pursing both careers for quite a while and consequently much of my anxiety ceased and a constructive plan was evolved. Warbuton (1992:4) compares an individual's use of philosophy in this way with servicing a car. To carry on living without checking one's assumptions is like driving a car without getting it serviced. This can apply not only to factual assumptions like the ones given earlier but also to examining one's values, one's options in life, one's actions and how they all fit together. In therapy the client's values can be made explicit and examined and used as the basis for assessing alternatives facing the client. There is not space here to develop the idea further, but hopefully enough has been said to establish that there is much promise in this approach.

 

Having made the case for such a philosophical approach to counselling, some limitations must be acknowledged. How effective it will be in specific cases depends on several factors, such as how willing and able the client is to look at their life. How successful it is in general depends on which model of the person is the more accurate. The greater the extent that Freud or the behaviourists are right the more limited use it will be. For if action is caused by unconscious motivation or learned behaviour then examining one's life in a rational way is not going to be so effective.

 

It would also be wrong to suggest that this approach is completely value-free. Socrates said "the unexamined life is not worth living" (Plato, 1969:72) but this statement itself is more often quoted than examined. Why exactly shouldn't one live a carefree, unreflective life ? Warbuton's analogy of a car being serviced is not entirely valid. A serviced car functions better ( usually !) but in what way does a counselled person function better ? There are two criticisms lurking here, one empirical and the other philosophical. Examining one's life in counselling may benefit the client in a number of ways, but one can imagine cases where it could be counter-productive. For example there is some research that suggests that the happiest people may be those who are a little deluded and overoptimistic (Argylle, 1987) and so not those who have examined their lives most carefully. The lesson to be learnt from this objection is that reflecting on life should not be done purely for its own sake but rather to promote the client's well-being. The philosophical objection is harder to repel. For it can be suggested that getting the client to lead the examined life faces the same risk as the existentialist or utilitarian counsellor discussed above. It is tempting to argue that full respect is paid to the client because one is getting them to work on their own values and assumptions. Though this may be a lesser imposition than if one suggests they should, for example, pursue pleasure, the implied values of this approach - for example self-reflection, consistency, clarity and self-knowledge - are qualities not valued by all cultures, individuals or, for that matter, clients.

 

Finally I cannot claim that this approach to counselling is entirely novel. Aspects of it are of course implicit in both the existential and the cognitive-behavioural approaches. What I have stressed is that this approach is primarily philosophical and that there is a way of counselling that is philosophical without it necessarily being existential or cognitive. There is a more basic way in which counsellors can use philosophy without having to agree with Heidegger or John Stuart Mill.

 

Conclusions

 

To conclude, philosophy is certainly an undervalued resource for the counsellor. Its analysis of concepts is critically important in the theory of counselling. In counselling practice, philosophical theories about the good life and other goals of therapy can be used, with caution, as part of the counsellor's body of knowledge. More generally, a philosophical approach to a client's life can be commended as a means to the client leading a more examined life. Ironically, philosophy in its role on the sidelines criticising counselling can be used against philosophy when it is brought into the counselling session itself. As counsellors faced with the necessary task of helping the many clients in distress we must navigate the rocky path between van Deurzen Smith's worthy plea for counsellors to "seriously investigat[e] what life is about and what people can do to live it better" [1994:16] and Wittgenstein's cautionary dictum that "What we cannot speak about we must pass over in silence" [1921:6.53].

 

References

Argylle, M (1987) The Psychology of Happiness Routledge

Deurzen-Smith , E. van (1994) Can Counselling Help School Of Education, University of Durham

Deurzen-Smith , E. van (1988) Existential Counselling In Practice Sage

Deurzen-Smith , E. van (1990) Existential Therapy in Individual Therapy ed. Dryden (Oxford University Press)

Egan, G (1975) The Skilled Helper Brooks/Cole

Heaton, J (1990 )What is Existential Analysis ? Journal of the Society for Existential Analysis 1: 2-6

Holmes, J & Lindley, R (1989) The Values of Psychotherapy Oxford University Press

LeBon, T (1994) The Existential Greyhound ( or how Jean-Paul Sartre goes to the White City and loses all his money) Philosophy Now 9

Plato (1969) The Apology Penguin Classics

Purton, P(1993) Philosophy and Counselling ( p 152- 170) In B. Thorne & W.Dryden (eds) Counselling: Interdisciplinary Perspectives Oxford University Press

Sartre, J.P. (1956) Being and Nothingness New York

Warburton, N (1992) Philosophy - The Basics Routledge

Wittgensein, L (1921) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus trans. D.Pears and B.McGuiness (Routledge and Kegan Paul, London 1961)

Wittgenstein, L (1980) Culture and Value Oxford Blackwell

 ©Tim LeBon